Competition Rules
The competition will be made of four different
tracks, each of them divided into sub-tracks
corresponding to various extension semantics. For each
sub-track, between one and four reasoning tasks must be solved. This page
describes these (sub-)tracks and the reasoning tasks,
as well as the scoring rules.
Abstract Argumentation
We recall here the definition of Dung's Abstract
Argumentation Frameworks (AFs) [Dung 95], as well as extension semantics.
An AF is a directed graph F = (A,R) where A is a set of
abstract entities called arguments, and R ⊆ A
× A is the attack relation. For a,b ∈ A,
we say that a attacks b when (a,b) ∈ R. If in addition b
attacks c, for some c ∈ A, then a defends c
against b. These concepts can be extended to sets of
arguments: S ⊆ A attacks (respectively defends) an
argument b ∈ A if there is some a ∈ S that attacks
(respectively defends) b. Now we can introduce basic
requirements that must be satisfied by a set of arguments in
order to be acceptable. A set S ⊆ A is
- conflict-free (S ∈ cf(F)) if S does not attack any of its
elements;
- admissible (S ∈ ad(F)) if S ∈ cf(F)
and S defends all its elements against all their attackers.
Finally, S
⊕ = S ∪ { a ∈ A | S attacks a
} is called the
range of S.
From these basic concepts, several semantics can be
defined. A set S ⊆ A is
- a complete extension (S ∈ co(F)) if S
∈ ad(F) and S contains all the arguments that it defends;
- a preferred extension (S ∈ pr(F)) if S
∈ ad(F) and for every S' such that S ⊂ S', S'
∉ ad(F);
- a stable extension (S ∈ st(F)) if S ∈
cf(F) and S attacks each argument not in S;
- a semi-stable extension (S ∈ sst(F)) if S
∈ co(F) and for every S' such that S⊕ ⊂
S'⊕, S' ∉ co(F);
- a stage extension (S ∈ stg(F)) if S
∈ cf(F) and for every S' such that S⊕ ⊂
S'⊕, S' ∉ cf(F);
- an ideal extension (S ∈ id(F)) if S ∈
ad(F), S is included in every preferred extension, and there
is no S' ∈ ad(F) included in every preferred extension
such that S ⊂ S'.
Among these semantics only the stable semantics can produce no
extension. For the semantics except the ideal semantics,
there may be several extensions. Only the ideal semantics
gives exactly one extension for any AF. See [Dung 95, Caminada et al 12, Verheij 96, Dung et al 07] for more details.
Assumption-based Argumentation
Now we present Assumption-based Argumentation (ABA) [Bondarenko et al 97] and
the corresponding semantics.
An ABA framework is a tuple F = (L,R,A,‾) where
- L is a set of literals
- R is a set of rules
- A ⊆ L is a (non-empty) set of assumptions
- ‾ is a mapping from assumptions to literals, that
represents a notion of contrariness
A rule x
0 ← x
1,...,x
n is made of
literals x
0, x
1,... x
n ∈ L, and n
≥ 0. A rule x
0 ← can be understood as a
fact, or alternatively x
0 ← ⊤. We
consider only
flat ABA frameworks,
i.e.
ABA frameworks where there is no assumption in the head of a
rule, which means no rule x
0 ←
x
1,...,x
n such that x
0 is
an assumption. A
deduction for a literal x ∈ L, supported by
X
L and X
R is a finite tree rooted in
x, with nodes labeled by symbols in L (or ⊤), and
such that
- each leaf is either a symbol in XL or
⊤,
- for each non-leaf node, with label x', its children are
x1,...,xn such that the rule x' ←
x1,...,xn is in XR.
Then, given a literal x ∈ L, an argument for x, supported
by the set of assumptions X
A, is a deduction for
x supported by X
A (and some rules X
R).
This is denoted X
A ⊢ x. Given two arguments
Arg
1 = A
1 ⊢ x
1 and
Arg
2 = A
2 ⊢ x
2, we
say that Arg
1 attacks Arg
2 if
x
1 is the contrary of some assumption in
A
2. Now, notions of attacks and defense between
sets of assumptions can be introduced, in order to define
extension semantics for ABA frameworks.
- A set of assumptions A1 attacks a set of
assumptions A2 if an argument supported by a
subset of A1 attacks an argument supported by a
subset of A2;
- A set of assumptions A1 defends an assumption
a if A1 attacks every set of assumption that
attacks a.
Then, extension semantics can be defined for an ABA framework.
In particular, given X
A ⊆ A,
- XA ∈ cf(F) if it does not attack any of
its elements;
- XA ∈ ad(F) if XA ∈ cf(F)
and XA defends all its elements;
- XA ∈ co(F) if XA ∈ ad(F)
and XA contains all the assumptions that it defends;
- XA ∈ pr(F) if it is a ⊆-maximal
admissible set of F;
- XA ∈ st(F) if XA ∈ cf(F)
and XA attacks every assumption in A ∖ XA.
Reasoning Tasks
We introduce the four reasoning tasks of the
competition:
- CE-σ
- Given an AF F = (A,R), give the number of σ-extensions of F.
- SE-σ
- Given an AF F = (A,R), give one σ-extensions of F.
- DC-σ
- Given an AF F = (A,R) and an argument a ∈ A, is a
credulously accepted in F?
- DS-σ
- Given an AF F = (A,R) and an argument a ∈ A, is a
skeptically accepted in F?
These problems can be equivalently defined for ABA
frameworks, considering F = (L,R,A,‾) instead of
F = (A,R), and an assumption instead of an argument
for DC-σ and DS-σ.
Tracks
Static Abstract Argumentation
The Static Abstract Argumentation track is divided into
six sub-tracks, corresponding to the following
semantics: complete (co), preferred (pr), stable (st),
semi-stable (sst), stage (stg) and ideal (id). For
σ ∈ { co, pr, st, sst, stg}, the
four problems CE-σ, SE-σ, DC-σ and
DS-σ will be considered. For σ = id, only
SE-σ and DS-σ will be considered (since
CE-σ is always trivially 1, and DS-σ
coincides with DC-σ).
Dynamic Abstract Argumentation
The Dynamic Abstract Argumentation track is divided into
three sub-tracks, corresponding to the complete (co),
preferred (pr) and stable (st) semantics. For each of
them, we consider the dynamic version of the four
problems CE-σ, SE-σ, DC-σ and
DS-σ: the solver must solve the given problem for
an input AF, and then solving it again for a sequence of
updates of the AF. An update can be:
- the addition of an attack between two existing
arguments;
- the deletion of an attack between two existing
arguments;
- the addition of a new argument, as well as a set
of incident attacks;
- the deletion of an existing argument, as well as
all the incident attacks.
Structured Argumentation
The Structured Argumentation track is divided into
three sub-tracks, corresponding to the complete (co),
preferred (pr) and stable (st) semantics. Each sub-track
is made of four reasoning tasks, namely CE-σ,
SE-σ, DC-σ and DS-σ.
Approximate Algorithms
A track dedicated to approximate algorithms is
included for the first time at ICCMA. For this
exploratory track, we restrict the reasoning tasks to
only two: the decision problems DC-σ and DS-σ, for five different sub-tracks:
σ ∈ { co, pr, st, sst, stg }, as well
as DS for the sub-track σ = id. We will
evaluate the solvers with respect to their accuracy,
i.e. the ratio of instances that are correctly
solved. The main interest of approximate algorithms over
exact algorithms is their (potentially) lower
runtime. Thus, the timeout will be 60 seconds, contrary
to the other tracks.
Solver Interface
See the Solver Requirements.
Scoring Rules
The scoring rules are different for exact algorithms
(i.e. the tracks on static/dynamic abstract
argumentation and structured argumentation) and
approximate algorithms. Let us start with exact
algorithms. For each sub-track:
- in case of any wrong result, the solver is
excluded from the sub-track;
- for every correct answer within the runtime limit
(600 seconds),
the solver gets a score of 1; in case of timeout or
non-parsable output, the score is 0;
- the cumulated runtime over the correctly solved
instances is used for breaking ties.
For approximate algorithms, the scoring rule is
slightly different. For each sub-track:
- for every correct answer within the runtime limit
(60 seconds), the solver gets a score
of 1;
- for every incorrect answer, timeout or non-parsable
output, the score is 0;
- the cumulated runtime over the correctly solved
instances is used for breaking ties.
References
-
[Dung 95] P. M. Dung, On the Acceptability of Arguments and its Fundamental Role in Nonmonotonic Reasoning, Logic Programming and n-Person Games. Artif. Intell. 77(2): 321-358 (1995)
-
[Caminada et al 12] M. Caminada, W. Carnielli, P.
Dunne, Semi-stable semantics. J. Log. Comput. 22(5): 1207-1254 (2012)
-
[Verheij 96] B. Verheij, Two approaches to
dialectical argumentation: admissible sets and
argumentation stages. Proc. of NAIC'96: 357-368 (1996).
-
[Dung et al 07] P. M. Dung, P. Mancarella, F. Toni, Computing ideal sceptical argumentation. Artif. Intell. 171(10-15): 642-674 (2007)
-
[Bondarenko et al 97] A. Bondarenko, P. M. Dung, R. Kowalski, F. Toni, An Abstract, Argumentation-Theoretic Approach to Default Reasoning. Artif. Intell. 93: 63-101 (1997)